|
|
|||
ИССЛЕДОВАНИЯ - КОММЕНТАРИИ - ССЫЛКИ Willemien Otten The anthropology of Johannes Scottus Eriugena Willemien Otten. *The Anthropology of Johannes Scottus Eriugena.* Brill Studies in Intellectual History, v. 20. Leiden: Brill, 1991. ISBN 90 04 09302 8. Reviewed by Eugene Vance, University of Washington To the extent
that the "history of ideas" in the narrow sense-- that is, the study
of tangible "sources and influences" as a way of grasping the meaning
or assessing the importance of a given work-- prevails in a modern
approach to John Scot Eriugena, the ninth-century translator, poet
and philosopher, his *Periphyseon* can only remain ambiguous, and
may indeed be easily consigned to a place of minor importance. The
*Periphyseon* may not have often read or closely followed by many
theologians of the centuries to follow. Nor, when it was read, do
we know to what extent it might have been perceived as a performance
of great virtuosity in its own right. Eriugena was an early
translator and importer of Gregory of Nyssa, Dionysius and Maximus
the Confessor into the language and hegemonic discourse(s) of Latin
theology, hence, a major mediator of ideas and human values that would
gain much acceptance in later medieval and renaissance culture. However,
since Eriugena used much of what he translated in the *Periphyseon*,
the directness of his own contributions to later expressions of those
same ideas and values is difficult to measure. In modern times, how
many people in our century have had enough time and enough Latin to
read the work as a whole? And for those who, like me, have relied
on the recent Sheldon- In this articulate
and readable book, Willamien Otten recognizes from the outset the
necessity of fully grasping the plan of the *Periphyseon* as a dynamic
performance before attempting to interpret the meanings of this or
that local passage. In this kind of work, ideas that unfold on a page
do not have a simple face value-- they co-signify as parts of a dynamic
system. Willamien Otten announces her intentions thus (p.
1): "Of Eriugena's works the *Periphyseon,* the *magnum opus* of this
ninth century Irish philosopher and theologian, will be the centre
of my attention. While analyzing the *Periphyseon,* interpreters of
Eriugena's philosophy have had to stretch their magination to
the utmost to include its five books in one philosophical frame
of reference, and have often failed. Therefore I have taken my starting-point
in the *Periphyseon*'s unbroken literary structure, thereby trying
to give an analysis of the author's overall ideas. In doing so, I
have been led to choose one central theme, namely the study of Eriugena's
anthropology...." What better "theme" than that of anthropology
to explore the poetics of a masterpiece that dares to negotiate the
radical tensions between the serene humanism of Byzantine Christian
Platonism and the more austere vision of human alienation and sin
inherent to the Augustinian West? We are lead quickly to see,
however, that Eriugena's anthropology is certainly no mere "theme,"
nor, in her terms, a "direct topic of discussion" (1). Indeed,
"the position of man as the leading character in the vast universe
Eriugena vokes was only gradually revealed...[and] put a definite
stop to any distinction between man as the object and man as the subject
of Eriugena's thought, making him instead the overall centre of the
*Periphyseon*'s universe. With this unifying view of man as
the central character in the *Periphyseon*'s literary structure, I
think we can legitimately regard the work as a coherent exposition
of ideas" (2). Preferring, thus, to analyze the *Periphyseon* on its
own terms, Otten forthrightly refuses to "explain his ideas as predominantly
based on outside influences. I hold that as Already in
her introduction we see that Otten's own thinking and writing resonate
with with certain broader discursive features of Eriugenian thought.
I find the following sentences stirring: "However, despite the gigantic
scope of nature, it appears that the human mind, while contained by
it like the rest of the world Although my own competence in questions of Eriugena's use of sources is limited (especially in the case of of works like Maximus's *Ambigua*, which seem never to have been translated into any modern language!), I am not wholly at ease with some of Otten's rather casual laying out of categories-- especially that of "the age of the Fathers." Otten writes, "For Eriugena the central problem is not why God brought evil into this world, but rather why it is that man lacks the means to execute his creative potential as the image of God in a near-divine attempt to restore the world to its original beauty. It is this shift of perspective that seems to distinguish Eriugena from his patristic predecessors" (5). From all of his patristic predecessors? From some (like Augustine) much more than from others (like Maximus?). Although Otten tends to play down the the underlying tensions between Eriugena's Eastern and Western patristic sources, these tensions cannot fail to surface later in her book, especially when she discusses the nature and role of sin in salvation history. Otten's prose is dense and competent, and she is good at both generating extended arguments and summarizing them as she takes a new step forward. She keeps to a uniform pacing of ideas as she as she progresses through the body of her text. For these reasons, I have found it difficult in what follows to excerpt ideas from her text and to summarize and simplify her complex arguments as they unfold in chapters of unwieldy length. I should perhaps add that in this review I shall adhere to Otten's use of the word "man" to imply (as does the Latin *homo*) humanity, and not maleness as gender. Chapter 1 stresses to what extent Eriugena's concept of nature is determined by the rational powers of the human mind itself as it ponders nature. If Eriugena posits the first division of nature into things that are and that are not, then his concept of nature derives not from what is intrins ic to nature, but from the rational powers of the soul that makes such discernments in the first place. If follows that the power of God's non-being to elude human thought is a sign of God's excellence and of the superiority of his non-being to being. "The divine excellence discloses a surplus of being, the overflowing profusion of which allows for and guarantees the existence of all other forms of being" (11). Otten continues by showing how the four subsequent modes by which the mind interprets the divisions of nature are subordinate to and implicated in the first. However, the structure of rational thought does not by itself determine the structure of nature, but is determined, in its capacities to act, by a divine plan rooted in God: "Thus we can in fact assemble all four modes of nature into an array of consecutive stages which at root expresses but a single development, namely that through which God unfolds himself in his creation" (38). Only at the last phase of that plan, when all things reach the return to God to which they aspire-- the return to *natura non creans et non creata*-- are the powers of division and analysis that characterize human rationality exhausted and fulfilled, that is, "when all of creation will have been led back to God in such a manner that there is not distinction whatsoever separating cause and effect" (38). Chapter 2
opens with a discussion of the congruence of modes of being and with
modes of thought, of *esse* with *comprehendi*. Otten evokes the dynamism
that links them as complementary processes comprising the divine plan.
If being is that which can be understood, "by consciously integrating
non-being into *natura* as its object of investigation, reason allows
the totality of nature actually to stretch into infinity. Eriugena
can be seen to employ the predicate of *non esse* for God as well
as for the reasons and essences of created being, since they all
transcend the grasp of the human mind" (43). However, it is still
through negation that Eriugena "secures the unreachableness of God
lest he should be compromised by condescending to the level of creation"
(47). Otten then gives a clear and succinct sketch of Eriugena's sense
of the complementarity of the aphophatic and kataphatic In Chapter
3, Otten restates Eriugena's inevitable insistence upon the negative
way as the final way of knowing, hence upon the shortcomings of created
language. But she does so only to bring more care to evoking the possibilities
and limits of Eriugena's concepts of theophany and, indeed, of the
dynamism of nature itself as theophanic and leading toward the eschatological
union of creation with the divine (87). Otten describes how
the principles of procession and return which relate the creation
to the creator are matched by the rational powers of dialectics as
a "theophanic art" (91). Otten then addresses the relationship between
dialectics and that other important theophanic power, Scripture, which
is knowable not only in letter but, just as importantly, through allegory.
Not only are the human mind and nature ordained to each other, but
"for its effective unfolding universal nature appears to rely ultimately
on the integrity of human nature.... Forming in itself but a
small section of natura In Chapter
4, a bit merciless in length (71 pp), Otten moves the discussion away
from "the broad contours of the Eriugenian universe" to deepen our
understanding of the role of man in that universe, that is, "how the
universe, by which is indicated the complete span of its dialectical
development, is essentially tailored to the scope of man's rational
capacities" (118). "Man stands at the crossroads of *natura*'s development,
as procession is about to turn effectively into its dialectical countermovement
of *reditus*. If man was created with such a place in *natura*, how
is this complicated by the fact of his sinful nature? Given the dialectical
structure of nature, of man's mind, and of Eriugena's own thought,
sin comes to play a positive role in the unfolding of nature: "In
this manner the problem of in can be seen to function as a kind
of catalyst for *natura*'s eschatological apotheosis in the *Periphyseon*.
One may indeed wonder what, in the imaginary case of an eternally
impeccable human nature, would have stopped the universe from going
around in endless circular repetitions" (123). In other words, sin
is part of the temporal economy of salvation-- of a divine plan of
salvation that is also a human history. Given the correspondences
Otten begins her tracing of man's itinerary in God's plan by returning to Eriugena's treatment of man's dual role as an animal among other animals and a s and a being made in God's image. The last object of the divine creation, man was created as a rational animal. "Sin merely occurred when man's rational character surrendered to irrational passions, for which it received proper punishment" (140). At this point, the procession of being in the creation has ended, and man has become an object of *natura creata et non creans*. Otten is not
concerned to explore how Eriugena might be at great pains, in his
discussions of the creation of man and of sin, to mediate carefully
between his affinities for Eastern humanism and the burden of Augustinianism.
Like Augustine, Eriugena discriminates between man's character as
image of God and the bodily man cleaved into two sexes, who procreates
bestially, who must eat and drink, etc. Allegorically, Paradise may
be identified with human nature, with man equated with the mind, and
woman the senses. With sin, man falls from intellect into the senses,
where he is dominated by carnal concupiscence and delight ( 171).
Such grounds are common to both traditions. However, Eriugena
seems to part ways with Augustine when the former argues that the
sinning body of humanity is a physical body superadded to man's spiritual
body at the time of sin (146). (Some careful comparisons between In this manner Eriugena inaugurates a new beginning for mankind, in which the disastrous effects of sin are overcome not so much by the external infusion of grace but by an internal remedy in the form of intellectual insight" (187). This implies man's coming to a full understanding of his own powers as a rational creature. In Chapter 5, "Back to God. The Final Reditus of Man and Nature," Otten recapitulates her trajectory of earlier chapters. Because the ideas involved are grandiose and majestic, I welcomed the repetition as she shows once again, and in considerable detail, how exegesis, allegory, analogy and dialectical argumentation are carefully interwoven by Eriugena to evoke the psychological and ontological conditions under which man-- and, through man, the whole of nature-- may return to God. Though sin eclipsed the divine powers of rationality in humanity, the expulsion man from Paradise was also the beginning of the return to God (197), and the labor of woman in childbirthis, alle gorically, the difficulty of ratiocination in the fallen world (199). At the return to God, humanity will enjoy immediate perception of things. However, in all of modes of human understanding, rationality remains a common denominator-- indeed, the way and the truth of man's perfection as a natural image of God. However, man
is no mere object of the creation: ontologically, he is among the
primordial causes, which is to say that he is nothing less than a
notion in the divine mind. "Made in the image of God, man is
not only an eternal idea in the divine mind, but he also contains
in his own mind all the images and notions of created things" (199).
Intelligibility and ontology are inseparable, and for man to investigate
nature properly is to fulfill its existence. If the very necessity
of understanding is a consequence of sin (201), on the other side
of the question, ignorance is also the potential for knowledge and
the affirmation of free will as the cause for achieving knowledge.
What is more, not just knowledge, but self-knowledge-- that is to
say, man's understanding of himself as being made in God's image--
"must give direction to Eriugena's infinite universe as a whole, because
it foreshadows the future *reditus* (206). "It is in man's thinking
that we can trace the movement of *processio* and *reditus* as the
universe's line of direction and in the end it is to man's speculation
on the self that we are led to find that movement's roots" (207).
Man's being and his understanding are interchangeable and identical,
and man's intelligence gives him the absolute certainty of his being
(209). Even though that intelligence was marred by sin, an *appetitus
beatitudinis* endured in the human soul in spite of sin (210).
Otten very briefly dissociates the Eriugenian *cogito* from the Cartesian
interpretation of it (210), but I wish that distinction had been developed,
if only from a pedagogical point of view: to do so would give us a
much clearer guidepost for situating our own post - So too, Eriugena's daring conflation of theophany and theosis, or deification (217), is a gesture that must have shocked the Augustinians in his midst-- even though such suppositions were strongly anchored in his Greek-speaking Platonic philosophical and Orthodox forebears. The twin processes of theophany and deification occur in three phases, and Otten summarizes these in the following terms: "...the first phase involves the transition of the mind, which is human nature in its purest form (i.e. its capacity as bearer of the divine image), to a state of total comprehension of the things that are below God. The following stage is the transition from *scientia* to *sapientia*, that is the contemplation of the intimate truth, albeit on the condition that it will indeed be granted to created nature. The final stage, which pertains only to the purest of minds, is when the human mind, like the sun, will appear to set (*occasus*) in God himself; it is the stage where man is confronted with the darkness of the inaccessible light. But the night will then become illuminated as if it were day" (218). Though Otten is not concerned with such questions, I am struck by the coherence of an epistemological agenda that stretches back to Plato's *Republic* and resonates afresh here in the Latin West. Conspicuously absent here is the Augustinian insistence upon grace as the only condition of illumination. On the other hand, what lacks in the *Periphyseon*, from the Dionysian perspective, is Eriugena's apparent reluctance to exalt erotic desire as a sacred impulse in the human soul. When I first read the *Periphyseon* (in translation), and while I read Otten's book, I only one thinker and writer in the West came to mind whose anthropology matches his, and that is Dante. However much Dante scholars themselves are wary of identifying the *Periphyseon* as a direct model for Dante's own anthropology as it matured in the *Paradiso*, I suspect that Eriugena's writing was an important part of Dante's later anthropological vision. To conclude, Otten has given us a tenacious and lucid reading of the *Periphyseon*. She allo ws the grandeur of Eriugena's humanism speak for itself. The strength of her book is its assiduity in following the inner thread of Eriugena's discourse, showing, as she progresses, what choices Eriugena must have made in order to resolve many inherited conflicts and contradictions. Otten has grasped the poetics of the *Periphyseon*-- by which, I mean the internal laws of its discursive production-- in a way that students of "literature" will not fail to admire. The *Periphyseon* has, indeed, a boldness and adventuresomeness much more characteristic of epic poetry than of theology. Inevitably, Otten's refusal to be distracted by larger cultural issues at work in the *Periphyseon* is both a strength and a limitation of her book. What does not come across in her book is an appreciation of the *Periphyseon*'s status as a major cultural event, one that synthesizes traditions that historically have remained at odds with each other even to the present day. This kind of range is best exemplified in the distinguished and lucid scholarship of Stephen Gersh, which Otten knows but does not exploit. Nor does Otten
involve herself closely with Eriugena's rhetoric. As is the
case with all of Eriugena's major sources, both Eastern and Western,
his theology is a highly rhetorical one, and at times Eriugena's rhetorical
virtuosity is not only stunning, but integral to the expression of
his negative theology. So too, Otten shuns examining the lexical reverberations
of Eriugena's Latin, with respect to his Hebrew, Greek and Latin forebears.
Almost all of the Latin quotations to which Otten refers are buried
in an appendix to her book. However, let us not criticize a
good book for what it does not do; rather, let us be grateful for
its success in achieving its purpose-- in this instance, an exalted
one. |
Все содержание (C) Copyright РХГИ, 1996 - 2001
Вернуться на ( начальную страницу ) (список авторов)